Aristotle
Essay by review • November 17, 2010 • Essay • 521 Words (3 Pages) • 1,218 Views
The last of Aristotle's claims that we will consider concerns one of Aristotle's many criticisms of Plato's theory of Forms. In the last paragraph on p. 267 (which begins "Further according to the assumptionÐ'...) Aristotle attempts to refute Plato's conception of the Forms by showing that the Forms share in their particulars just as their particulars share in them. On his account, Plato's theory would generate an infinite regress consisting of an unlimited number of Forms. At about 991a in the Metaphysics, claims that a Form, being predicated of a number of things and existing separately from them, will necessitate something else that is predicated of that Form and all of its particulars. If there is a group of men, they are presumed to be men in virtue of their participation in the Form of Man. This Form, however, must be another example of a man, since it is like all the other examples found in the particulars. Thus, a Form of the Form of Man is needed, and this Form of the Form will itself need a Form. This process will continue forever, involving an infinite regress. is necessitated. Aristotle claims, in short, that the Forms are patterns not only of particular sensible things, but of themselves as well. (990a 30). Any significance that the Forms could hold is lost if there is nothing to distinguish them from particulars. A Form must be, by definition, the single paradigm of a certain class of things. This regress claims that there would have to be multiple Forms for the same class, and even Forms of Forms, making them particulars at the same time. If this is true, then Forms cannot exist in the way Plato conceived of them.
This criticism of Plato's Forms shows that Aristotle grossly misunderstands Plato's conceptions of the Forms. Plato makes it clear that the relationship between Form and particular is not reciprocal. While a sensible thing is like a Form, a Form is never like a sensible thing in return, because it is a fundamental property of a Form that it is unique, so nothing else can be like it. It is a part of what it is to be a particular to imitate the ideal example of the form. By contrast the Form is the absolute perfect example of the genus it is predicated of, so it cannot be "like" something else, since being "like" something indicates some defect in imitation, particularly in the sense Plato uses it. Plato's conception of the Forms contains the
...
...