Categorical Imperative
Essay by review • December 21, 2010 • Essay • 2,002 Words (9 Pages) • 2,404 Views
To begin with, Kant draws an analogy between the laws of ethics and the laws of science. Just as the
laws of science can be known by pure reason, the laws of ethics, or morality, can be known by
practical reason. Morality, though, is a normative system, as opposed to the natural laws of science. A
normative system prescribes what ought to happen, as opposed to a natural system that determines
what actually does happen. Since morality only cares for what ought to happen and not with what
actually happens, moral laws, then, must be found a priori. Everything a posteriori or discovered with
the senses only shows with did happen, not what ought to have happened. Moral laws must not be
derived from examples, since moral laws would hold even if there were no examples. Therefore, the
foundation of morality for Kant must lie with reason alone. Rationality is the key to morality. Based
on this premise, it follows that all rational beings must have the same moral laws, and all moral laws
would have absolute necessity that would apply universally to all rational beings.
An action to have moral worth, besides being a universal law, also must come from duty and duty
alone. Duty is the cause of an action when it is done purely out of respect for the law. Kant
distinguishes between two kinds of duties: perfect and imperfect duties. A perfect duty is one where
people are not treated as a means to an end, while imperfect duties involve treating people as ends. To
not tell lies is an example of a perfect duty, since when one tells a lie, one is using the other person as
a means to one's end. To be beneficent and charitable to others is an imperfect duty. Even though not
helping others does not treat others as a means to one's end, it does not treat others as an end in
themselves. When perfect and imperfect duties conflict, Kant believes that perfect duties override
imperfect duties. In other words, it is more important to not treat someone as a means than it is to treat
someone as an end. For example, one must tell the truth even if in so doing, one hurts someone's
feelings and is a catalyst to their suicide.
To follow duties, rational beings have wills. A will that accords with duty is the only unconditional
good, since only with a good will can any other good be achieved. From a good will come all other
goods. Since good comes from the will alone, the consequences of an action are irrelevant in
determining moral actions. A moral act is good in itself, so the end result of an action cannot be used
to justify the morality of an action. For example, lying cannot be justified as being moral or immoral
by observing the consequences from the action. These consequences are only the subjective ends that
arise from the particular situation. The basis of moral and practical must be from objective principles
that are universally valid for any rational being. Consequently, we cannot use subjective ends, that is
our inclinations or feelings in the determination of moral law, since these are contingent on specific
facts, while any moral law must apply to all rational beings.
Since morality lies with rationality, and a good will is necessary for duty to be followed, then the
purpose of reason is to produce a good will. Kant defines an imperative as a command that reason
gives to the will. There are two kinds of imperatives: hypothetical imperatives and categorical
imperatives. Hypothetical imperatives are based on some specific end or purpose: "If I want to get a
good grade, then I must write a good essay" or "if I want to sleep, then I must lie down." These
imperatives are conditional, since I may not want a good grade or want to sleep. But, moral laws
being universally applicable cannot depend on external facts, such as my desire for sleep. Desires,
inclinations, and anything other than reason, cannot be used to determine a moral law, since then the
law would be contingent on a person having a certain desire or inclination. Any moral law that must
necessarily be applied to all rational beings must come from reason alone. Therefore, no form of a
hypothetical imperative can be used as a basis for universal moral law.
The other type of imperative is then, the categorical imperative which is just one that does not
depend on some other end. A categorical imperative represents an action that is good and necessary in
itself. The idea of a categorical imperative is a purely formal idea, with the primary characteristic of
being universally applicable. All rational beings are held accountable to the categorical imperative,
and no exceptions can be made for any specific person or group of persons. To check whether any
maxim, or reason behind a possible action, can be considered a moral law, one attempts to fit the
maxim into the form of a categorical imperative. If the maxim cannot be thought of as a universal law,
applicable to all rational beings, then the maxim cannot be a moral law. For example, a maxim could
be breaking promises whenever one has the desire to do so. One instantly arrives
...
...