Ethics of Prostitution
Essay by review • March 2, 2011 • Essay • 1,217 Words (5 Pages) • 1,277 Views
Probably no one in the English-speaking world is unaware that our Governor
has spoken out on subjects where lesser mortals, especially politicians,
have held their tongue. His opinions on the assassination of JFK appear
to be well-founded (November '99), however, and his views about the
religious right seem equally appropriate (Holiday '99). Perhaps his
proposals for the legalization of pot and prostitution also deserve some
second thoughts.
The strongest argument against prostitution, no doubt, is its alleged
immorality. If this means no more than that most people THINK
prostitution is immoral, that appears to be correct. But if this is taken
to mean prostitution actually IS immoral, then an argument is required.
Believing something doesn't make it true. That the Sun revolves around
the Earth, which is immovable, are examples of false beliefs that once
were widely held.
That an activity is illegal does not establish that it is immoral, any
more than than its legality establishes its morality. Ownership of
slaves, among the most immoral of all activities, was legal before the
passage of the 13th Amendment, but illegal thereafter, even though its
moral status did not change. What is legal can be ascertained from
statutes in books of law, while the morality of an action presupposes a
suitable standard.
There are many claimants to that role, including subjective theories,
family-value theories, religious-based theories, and culture-relative
theories, according to which actions are right when you (your family, your
religion, or your culture) approve of them. So if you (your family, your
religion, or your culture) approve of incest, cannibalism, or sacrificing
virgins to appease the gods, those actions cannot be immoral. They are
moral, necessarily!
All of these approaches make morality a matter of power, where right
reduces to might. If someone approves of killing, robbing, or raping you,
you have no basis to complain on the ground that those actions are
immoral, if subjectivism is correct. Similarly for family, religion, and
culture-based alternatives. Every person, every family, every religion,
and every culture is equal, regardless of their practices, if such
theories are true.
As James Rachels, THE ELEMENTS OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY, has explained, on any
of these accounts, the very ideas of criticism, reform, or progress in
matters of morality no longer apply. If attitudes about right and wrong
differ or change, that is all there is to it, even when they concern your
life, liberty, or happiness. If some person, family, or group has the
power to impose their will upon you, these theories afford no grounds for
you to object.
Philosophers have therefore sought to establish some less-relative and
more-objective framework for understanding morality, including what are
known as consequentialist and non-consequentialist theories. According to
consequentialism, an action is RIGHT when it produces as much GOOD
(usually taken to be happiness) as any available alternative. But the
problem remains of deciding FOR WHOM that happiness ought to be produced.
According to Ethical Egoism, for example, an action is right if it brings
about as much happiness for you personally as any available alternative.
Consequences for others simply don't count. So Ted Bundy, John Gacy, and
Jeffrey Dahmer, for example, are home free--morally speaking--though few
juries would be likely to be impressed by the argument that killing gave
them more happiness than any available alternative.
According to Limited Utilitarianism, moreover, an action is right when it
brings about as much happiness for your group as any available
alternative. This is good news for The Third Reich, the Mafia, and
General Motors. If no available alternative would produce more happiness
for Nazis than territorial acquisition, military domination, and racial
extermination, then those qualify as moral actions, if Limited
Utilitarianism is correct.
Classic Utilitarianism, among consequentialist theories, is the only one
that dictates encompassing the effects actions have upon everyone rather
than some special class. But this virtue does not guarantee the right
result. If some social arrangement with a certain percentage of slaves,
say, 15%, would bring about greater happiness for the population as a
whole--because
...
...