ReviewEssays.com - Term Papers, Book Reports, Research Papers and College Essays
Search

Reproductive Cloning

Essay by   •  January 25, 2011  •  Essay  •  1,642 Words (7 Pages)  •  1,489 Views

Essay Preview: Reproductive Cloning

Report this essay
Page 1 of 7

Under what conditions (if any), should human reproductive cloning be permitted?

Kubiak, J.Z. and Johnson, M.H. (2001). Human Infertility, Reproductive Cloning and Nuclear Transfer: a Confusion of Meanings. Bioessays, 23(4), 359-64.

This article argues that confusions in the semantic meanings of human reproductive cloning may hinder future scientific progressions to discover an ethically viable solution to infertility treatments. Kubiak and Johnson postulates that the term “nuclear transfer” is different from “reproductive cloning” as the former method can generate a person who is not necessarily a “genetic clone”, but a genetic amalgamation of both parents. However, society interprets these two terms as synonyms. The Chief Medical Officer of Health in the United Kingdom recommended “The transfer of an embryo created by cell nuclear replacement into the uterus of a woman should remain a criminal offence”. The authors accept that nuclear transfer is not without its technical flaws, it is however unreasonable to place ethical and legal restraints on its future research because of its seemingly semantic synonymy with reproductive cloning. Furthermore, as UK holds considerable legal influence in the world, such legislation may see an international ban on a potentially beneficial and uncontroversial treatment for infertility.

The article is relevant to the current question and suggests that reproductive cloning may be condoned because �clones’ are not always the exact genetic replica of one person, and such method may also be a potential treatment for infertility. The arguments are persuasive as it provides a new insight into the definition of cloning, and holds validity since the former(biased) notion of reproductive cloning are cited in many articles. However, humans are still procreated under artificial means by this method regardless of their collective DNA structure, hence those produced nonetheless lack the link to the naturalness of their origins. The critical question then, is how might the new definition address teleological views on cloning.

Young, L. (2003). Scientific Hazards of Human Reproductive �Cloning’. Human Fertility, 6(2), 59-63.

This article presents various scientific objections to human reproductive cloning. The first objection is that reproductive cloning results in high level of developmental defects. For example, Dolly the sheep suffered from a species common lung tumour six years following its creation. However, since she was the only cloned sheep to have reached that age, there were insufficient information to determine whether such defect was directly attributable to cloning. The second objection is that most cloned foetuses die during gestation. Young argues that failure rates in animal studies are likely to be underestimates because there is a lack of procedural knowledge in somatic cell nuclear transfer for humans. Finally, Young contends that information which supports reproductive cloning lack scientific validity because they can only be found on websites. Specifically, he cited preimplantation genetic diagnosis (PGD), which reportedly allows scientists to screen and identify potential genetic defects in sheep embryos. Realistically however, Young affirms that there are species differences in geno makeup, and results derived from sheep studies cannot adequately be applied to humans. Collectively, Young concludes that the current scientific knowledge is insufficient to accurately determine the hazards associated with reproductive cloning. Hence, more knowledge is required before appropriate ethical judgements may be formed, and legislations are put in place.

This article is relevant because it presents the scientific conditions which currently disfavours reproductive cloning. The arguments are valid as the author takes an objective stance on the subject, citing evidence against reproductive cloning, but also outline the limitation of such arguments. The critical question asked is if the current scientific knowledge sufficiently determines that reproductive cloning is relatively safe, how will the ethical perspectives and public policies thus change to condone reproductive cloning?

Burley, J. (2002). The Ethics of Therapeutic and Reproductive Cloning. Seminars in Cell & Developmental Biology, 10, 287-294.

This paper addresses four ethical objections to reproductive cloning, and argues that they are invalid. Firstly, it is widely assumed that clones run the risk of being mentally or physically impaired (H1). Burley addresses this issue by postulating that parents who suffer inheritable diseases such as HIV or breast cancer also run the risk of procreating impaired children. By accepting H1, the society is effectively banning the rights for those parents to bear children. However, since such bans do not exist, H1 is also invalid to undermine reproductive cloning. The second common ethical objection alleges that clones may be victims of society’s harmful prejudice against their creation (H2). Burley rejects this view by arguing that H2 is insufficient to prohibit cloning since it can effectively ban the natural conception of mixed race children in societies that discriminate against interracial unions. The third issue asserts that clones will be harmed by the demands and expectations of their parents or genotype donors (H3). Again, this statement is invalid as Barley argues that girls who are brought up in traditionally female roles also face the potential harm from their parent’s demands and expectations. Since society hold no rules to ban the natural procreation of females, H3 becomes an invalid objection against reproductive cloning. The final objection contends that clones might be harmed by the awareness of their origins (H4). Burley challenges this view by arguing that if H4 holds true, then parents with criminal backgrounds should also be prevented from procreating naturally.

This article is well chosen as it invalidates the conditions which were set to prohibit reproductive cloning. However, current defences to cloning are only compared to natural norms. The critical question will then be: Given that reproductive cloning is perfected in humans, there will naturally be no genetic need for men. What ethical implications will it hold for the diminishing roles of male in the future.

Hayry, M. (2003). Philosophical Arguments for and Against Human Reproductive Cloning. Bioethics, 17, 447-460.

This article presents philosophical arguments for and against reproductive

...

...

Download as:   txt (11.1 Kb)   pdf (132.3 Kb)   docx (13 Kb)  
Continue for 6 more pages »
Only available on ReviewEssays.com