ReviewEssays.com - Term Papers, Book Reports, Research Papers and College Essays
Search

Slippery Slopes

Essay by   •  November 15, 2010  •  Essay  •  2,601 Words (11 Pages)  •  1,035 Views

Essay Preview: Slippery Slopes

Report this essay
Page 1 of 11

What is a slippery slope argument? Critically discuss the use of such arguments in one area of biomedical ethical controversy.

The slippery slope argument is amongst the strongest voiced and possibly the most emotive of arguments in opposition to legalising voluntary active euthanasia (VAE, the act of accelerating the death of another, usually by lethal injection, for their own good and with their consent). In fact, in discussion on practically any change in social policy it is common place to hear objections to the effect, "if this, then that, and finally that" . But how valid is this form of argument? To answer this question, I will examine the nature of the slippery slope argument in its two major forms (empirical and logical), see how it has been applied to the debate on permitting voluntary active euthanasia and determine the validity of these applications.

It is not easy to apply a strict definition to the term slippery slope argument as it is used so loosely . The image it conjures is that of speeding hastily out of control in a direction few would want to venture without a means of stopping. A paradigmatic form of the argument is suggested by Hartough :

I propose and you oppose that action A (let us say, voluntary active euthanasia) which

Ð'* is currently prohibited (this is not necessarily so, but is usually the case), yet

Ð'* is not deemed to be objectionable in itself by either you or myself and

Ð'* may be referred to as the top of the slippery slope

should, in fact, be permitted. Your objection arises because you believe that in allowing actions of type A, a causal mechanism exists (very much like a chain reaction) which will lead us to accept action N (e.g. the killing of incompetent patients who explicitly refuse euthanasia) which

Ð'* is clearly unacceptable to us both and

Ð'* lies at the bottom of the slope

The nature of the links (for example, killing people who are "not terminally ill or suffering [and then] those who cannot decide for themselves" , etc.), the force or causal mechanism forming the reaction (maybe the increasing disregard for the sanctity of life) and what lies at the bottom of the slope (mass genocide) is also proposed by he who puts forward the argument.

This causal (or empirical) form of the argument is distinguished from the logical form which basically states if we were committed to being rational and consistent (supposedly held to be rather agreeable traits) in our moral reasoning we would again end up at the squalid foot of the slope; if on some rationale we accept proposition A, then by the same rationale we are committed to accepting the closely related proposition B, accept B and we are committed to accepting C and right on through to N, which is clearly unacceptable. Therefore, we should not accept A. The important difference is that while the causal form of the argument depends on a prediction that if we accept A then we will, the world being the way it is, accept N, the logical form depends on a commitment to consistency and rationality in our decision making. It is, perhaps, interesting to note that the metaphor of the slippery slope becomes somewhat less relevant in relation to this logical form of the argument. A synonym of the slippery slope argument often used is the Ð''thin end of the wedge argument' and seems to me to better convey the irresistible force (as opposed to a lack of control) of logic which forms the thrust of the argument.

A discussion of some of the slippery slope arguments opposing voluntary active euthanasia that feature in the Assisted Dying and Terminally Ill Bill (ADTIB) provides a useful framework for critically assessing the validity of such arguments. The Bill sets out provisions under which, following its enactment, voluntary euthanasia may be legally performed by a medical doctor. The provisions require that, amongst other things: it is the patient himself who expresses the wish to be assisted to die; the patient is competent, has a terminal illness and is suffering unbearably as a result of that terminal illness.

One mechanism, it has been argued, that could lead us from VAE under the provisions of the Bill to an uncontrollable move towards less desirable forms of intentional killing is the "elastic interpretation" of vague terms contained within the provisions of the Bill. These terms include "competent", "unbearable suffering" and "terminal illness . Such a mechanism has been identified in the practice of abortion since its legalisation under the Abortion Act 1967. While the intention of the act was to permit abortion as an exceptional procedure in specific circumstances, at the last count as many as 180,000 abortions were carried out annually in the UK and are, according to Lord Walton, available "virtually . . . on demand" .

There are two points being made here; one is the hypothesis that due to the vague nature of the terms used, the intention of the Bill will be perverted in its application to practice. The second is the pointing to a past slide down a slippery slope in which the same mechanism was at work as evidence to increase the plausibility of this argument. I will deal with the latter first.

The main problem with this type of argument is that "while we may be able confidently to explain afterwards why things went wrong, that does not mean that we could confidently have predicted this beforehand" . I would agree that the similarities between the two bills, particularly the shared reason advanced in support of their introduction (that each would better regulate the illegal practice of abortion and euthanasia via legislation) highlight a need for caution. However, "given that our knowledge of social psychology is very limited" , it would be a mistake to attach too much weight to this tale from history, especially given that numerous other factors are at play. For example, "whereas it was, perhaps, to be expected that there would be growing pressures to apply the Abortion Act with growing elasticity in an age of increasing secularity, most people have a natural desire to remain alive" . Indeed, in any case in which we foresee our future destination would it not be wise to recall the advice of Perelman and Olbrechts-Tyteca, that "[s]tress will be laid on the ambiguity of development and, consequently, on the arbitrariness of seeing only a single direction."

Let us now return to the hypothesis itself; that the vague nature

...

...

Download as:   txt (14.7 Kb)   pdf (160.9 Kb)   docx (14.8 Kb)  
Continue for 10 more pages »
Only available on ReviewEssays.com